Sun Jan 30 13:47:55 2005 Cambridge Scientific Abstracts Marked Records Last Search Query: natsoulas, thomas Your Comments: Record 1 of 34 DN: Database Name PsycINFO (1840-Current) TI: Title The case for intrinsic theory: IX. further discussion of an equivocal remembrance account AU: Author Natsoulas, Thomas SO: Source Journal of Mind & Behavior. Vol 25(1), Win 2004, pp. 7-32 RL: Resource Location [URL:http://www.ume.maine.edu/~jmb/welcome.html] AB: Abstract I go on here with my endeavor to ascertain intrinsic-theoretical elements that are explicitly or implicitly present in O'Shaughnessy's (2000) remembrance account of inner awareness, or the immediate cognitive awareness that we have of some of our own mental-occurrence instances. According to an intrinsic theory of such awareness, a directly apprehended state of consciousness (to use James's concept) includes in its own structure inner awareness of itself. I seek to understand those distinct mental occurrence instances which O'Shaughnessy holds are the cognitive inner awarenesses of our experiences. They are memory experiences, he claims, owed to latent knowledge of one's experiences that is acquired automatically as a direct effect of their occurrence. These remembrances are more akin to thought experiences than to perceptual experiences that apprehend their objects directly; indeed, they seem to be, strictly, actualizations of conceptual capacities. So, queries regarding their contents revert to queries regarding the latent knowledge that informs them. How does our author propose one directly gains this latent knowledge of experiences? This question leads us back to what the cognitive effects may be of the purely extensional, non-intentional awareness... (PsycINFO Database Record (c) 2004 APA, all rights reserved) (journal abstract ) Record 2 of 34 DN: Database Name PsycINFO (1840-Current) TI: Title The Case for Intrinsic Theory: X. A Phenomenologist's Account of Inner Awareness AU: Author Natsoulas, Thomas SO: Source Journal of Mind & Behavior. Vol 25(2), Spr 2004, pp. 97-121 RL: Resource Location [URL:http://www.ume.maine.edu/~jmb/welcome.html] AB: Abstract This article is in large part an exposition and interpretation of the Woodruff Smith intrinsic-theoretical account of inner awareness. And, it is propaedeutic to considering, subsequently in the present series, the first of six theses regarding inner awareness that Kriegel defended in a recently published issue of this journal. Included here, as well, is some of the relevant background about intrinsic theory and other theories of inner awareness. Kriegel defended his first thesis with special critical reference to phenomenologist Woodruff Smith's theory, and maintained that, on the contrary, a conscious mental-occurrence instance presents itself, too: albeit secondarily, in the sense of its receiving less attention than does its primary object (e.g., the sun). Woodruff Smith conceived of inner awareness -- the apprehension that one immediately has, as they take place, of many of one's mental-occurrence instances -- to be part of the modality of presentation of a mental-occurrence instance's primary object. That is, the inner awareness intrinsic to a conscious mental-occurrence instance "modifies" (or "qualifies") the (sole) presentation in that mental-occurrence instance. 1 would like to put it for Woodruff Smith that inner awareness is the reflexive way in which a conscious mental-occurrence instance is an awareness of its primary object -- as the latter's being, inter alia, an object of this conscious mental-occurrence instance. However, his conception includes that every conscious mental-occurrence instance possesses a "phenomenal quality" -- which amounts to the instance's appearing in the mind -- and inner awareness is awareness of this appearance. This seems to mean a conscious mental-occurrence instance, too, is presented therein, contrary to both (a) that the presentation in any mental-occurrence instance is just of its primary object and (b) that the inner-awareness feature "modifies" the only presentation there is within a conscious mental-occurrence instance. (PsycINFO Database Record (c) 2004 APA, all rights reserved) (journal abstract ) Record 3 of 34 DN: Database Name PsycINFO (1840-Current) TI: Title The case for intrinsic theory: VII. An equivocal remembrance theory AU: Author Natsoulas, Thomas SO: Source Journal of Mind & Behavior. Vol 24(1), Win 2003, pp. 1-28 RL: Resource Location [URL:http://www.ume.maine.edu/~jmb/welcome.html] AB: Abstract B. O'Shaughnessy advocates an account of inner awareness (in the sense of the present series of articles) that I would categorize as a remembrance theory. It is these remembrances that are proposed to be one's inner awareness of one's experiences: occurrent non-inferential conceptual awarenesses of the latter. Although O'Shaughnessy argues contra one's having intrinsic occurrent conceptual inner awareness of one's experiences, he maintains that every experience is its own "extensional object" (which is distinct from its being its own intentional object, as an intrinsic theory of inner awareness would imply). This non-conceptual reflexive relation of an experience to itself--"one's experiential awareness of one's experiences"--is claimed by O'Shaughnessy to be a case of awareness in exactly the same sense that any basic perceptual experience is awareness of its extensional object. The present article and the next one in the present series comprise an attempt to explicate O'Shaughnessy's conception of inner awareness, in particular, aspects of the conception that may contribute to the positive case for intrinsic theory. (PsycINFO Database Record (c) 2004 APA, all rights reserved) Record 4 of 34 DN: Database Name PsycINFO (1840-Current) TI: Title The stream of consciousness: XXVL. Awareness as commentary (second part) AU: Author Natsoulas, Thomas SO: Source Imagination, Cognition & Personality. Vol 22(1), 2003, pp. 55-74 RL: Resource Location [URL:http://baywood.com/search/PreviewJournal.asp?qsRecord=4] AB: Abstract This article, published in two parts, is propaedeutic to a consideration next of Weiskrantz's conception of consciousness from a perspective bequeathed to us by James more than a century ago. Weiskrantz has argued in support of a general account of awareness that resembles the "Intellectualist" notion of mind against which James strongly objected. Weiskrantz mainly addressed the question of where in the brain the stream of consciousness "flows," but he also maintained at some length that all awarenesses, even those experiences that are involved in having pain, are matters of commentary. Contrary to how it may seem, every state of consciousness is in fact a certain kind of behavioral response-covert, overt, or incipient-that brings something or other under a heading. Although Weiskrantz explicitly rejected all eliminative strategies vis-a-vis awareness, he formulated his own concept of awareness in terms of the operations that allow him to judge whether a subject is aware of something in particular, and he claimed that awareness always consists either of the delivery of a report or an occurrent brain-state of readiness to issue a report. (PsycINFO Database Record (c) 2004 APA, all rights reserved) (journal abstract ) Record 5 of 34 DN: Database Name PsycINFO (1840-Current) TI: Title The stream of consciousness: XXVIL. Defending conscious experience AU: Author Natsoulas, Thomas SO: Source Imagination, Cognition & Personality. Vol 22(1), 2003, pp. 75-93 RL: Resource Location [URL:http://baywood.com/search/PreviewJournal.asp?qsRecord=4] AB: Abstract Weiskrantz's recent account of awareness is considered from a perspective that James bequeathed us. In opposition to the Intellectualists, James asks why a pure ego wielding purely conceptualizing acts is needed to give us awareness of relations and universals, inter alia. In opposition to Weiskrantz's Intellectualism, I ask how a commentary system, which has at its disposal only conceptual materials, can swoop down from on high to do the job of creating the experiences we undergo. Weiskrantz prefers the stronger of two positions concerning the relation of awareness to commentary that are consistent with his general view. On the minimal position, he would grant that experiences do takes place without commentary. However, no less so, he would conceive of consciousness as a matter of engaging in higher-order thought. He insists that one's firsthand apprehension of one's stream of experience or its components is carried out by, as it were, a higher agency: namely, a commentary system. Thus, none of our experiences is conscious unless appropriate judgment is passed upon it from outside and on high. (PsycINFO Database Record (c) 2004 APA, all rights reserved) (journal abstract ) Record 6 of 34 DN: Database Name PsycINFO (1840-Current) TI: Title What is this autonoetic consciousness? AU: Author Natsoulas, Thomas SO: Source Journal of Mind & Behavior. Vol 24(2), Spr 2003, pp. 229-254 RL: Resource Location [URL:http://www.ume.maine.edu/~jmb/welcome.html] AB: Abstract As Tulving argues, concepts shape psychologists' thinking and determine how the end products of research are recorded. Currently in prominent use is not only Tulving's concept of episodic memory but also his allied concept of autonoetic consciousness. And because, too, of the growing attention by psychologists to aspects of their subjects' consciousness streams, I explore Tulving's concept of autonoetic consciousness: to help improve the exercise of consciousness concepts in psychology generally. Two special topics among others are discussed: (a) the "flavor" Tulving claims characterizes recollective experience and corresponds to the warmth and intimacy James proposes consciousness states possess, and (b) whether the autonoetic-consciousness concept applies to a brain-damaged man said to lack, probably, any capability for autonoetic awareness. (PsycINFO Database Record (c) 2004 APA, all rights reserved) (journal abstract ) Record 7 of 34 DN: Database Name PsycINFO (1840-Current) TI: Title "Viewing the World in Perspective, Noticing the Perspectives of Things": James J. Gibson's Concept AU: Author Natsoulas, Thomas SO: Source Journal of Mind & Behavior. Vol 24(3-4), Sum-Fal 2003, pp. 265-288 RL: Resource Location [URL:http://www.ume.maine.edu/~jmb/welcome.html] AB: Abstract Gibson distinguishes among activities of the visual system, including viewing a room (say) as opposed to seeing it, and, in effect, between a visual-system activity and the stream of experience ("awareness-of") that is a product and part of it. During viewing, one perceives the surfaces ("here-and-now surfaces") projecting light to one's point of observation, and one's location in relation to them. Thus, one does not view some of the surfaces that one sees when, instead, one engages in straightforward seeing at the same observation point. The latter activity produces direct awareness of both occluded and here-and-now surfaces, although the latter surfaces are not distinguished as such (which occurs in viewing). Inter alia, it is argued that, given Gibson's account of visually controlled locomotion, viewing should be considered the visual perceptual activity involved therein since, in his view, one cannot see light and determine one's behavior on that basis. (PsycINFO Database Record (c) 2004 APA, all rights reserved) (journal abstract ) Record 8 of 34 DN: Database Name PsycINFO (1840-Current) TI: Title The Case for Intrinsic Theory: VIII. The Experiential in Acquiring Knowledge Firsthand of One's Experiences AU: Author Natsoulas, Thomas SO: Source Journal of Mind & Behavior. Vol 24(3-4), Sum-Fal 2003, pp. 289-316 RL: Resource Location [URL:http://www.ume.maine.edu/~jmb/welcome.html] AB: Abstract Discussion continues here of a theory (O'Shaughnessy, 2000) I have previously described as being an equivocal remembrance theory of inner awareness, the direct apprehension of one's own mental-occurrence instances (Natsoulas, 2001c). O'Shaughnessy claims that we acquire knowledge of each of our experiences as it occurs, yet any occurrent cognitive awareness of it that we may have comes later and is mediated by memory. Thus, acquiring knowledge of an experience firsthand is automatic and silent, not a matter of experientially apprehending the experience. Although O'Shaughnessy does hold that every experience has itself as an ("extensional") object, this is not a matter of a cognitive self-apprehension (as an intrinsic theory of inner awareness would maintain, e.g., Brentano, 1911/1973). O'Shaughnessy's grounds for his proposal of a nonexperiential acquisition of knowledge of one's experiences amounts to the claim that to hold otherwise would imply an infinite regress of experiences, for the experience by which we would know of an experience would be itself the object of experience, etc. I argue that neither an appendage theory (e.g., James, 1890/1950) nor an intrinsic theory of inner awareness, both of which are experiential, sets an experiential regress going. (PsycINFO Database Record (c) 2004 APA, all rights reserved) Record 9 of 34 DN: Database Name PsycINFO (1840-Current) TI: Title Freud and consciousness: XI. A different interpretation considered AU: Author Natsoulas, Thomas SO: Source Psychoanalysis & Contemporary Thought. Vol 25(1), Win 2002, pp. 29-66 RL: Resource Location [URL:http://www.iup.com/order.cfm?bookno=PC&action=info&J=J] AB: Abstract One major purpose of this series of articles is to convince readers that Freud does indeed qualify as "a sophisticated and relevant theorist of consciousness," as Dr. Paul Redding calls him in his essay "Freud's Theory of Consciousness" (2000). My effort continues here to provide as accurate a picture as I am able of Freud's conception of consciousness, with special reference to an interpretation of this conception other than the one I have been developing in the present series. I relate to in my analyses a distinction that Redding puts to central use between two kinds of consciousness, Reddingsuggests that Freud relied to good effect on this distinction in his account of the unconscious psychical processes. The distinction lies between two properties that belong to individual psychical processes: A psychical process is "phenomenally conscious" if there is something it is like to undergo it and "access conscious" if it is poised for use as a premise in reasoning and the rational control for action and speech. Freud's dynamically unconscious psychical processes are not "poised" repression prevents them from being accessed. But, according to Redding's understanding of Freud's theory, they nevertheless instantiate phenomenal consciousness. (PsycINFO Database Record (c) 2004 APA, all rights reserved) Record 10 of 34 DN: Database Name PsycINFO (1840-Current) TI: Title Freud and consciousness: XII. Agreements and disagreements AU: Author Natsoulas, Thomas SO: Source Psychoanalysis & Contemporary Thought. Vol 25(3), Sum 2002, pp. 281-328 RL: Resource Location [URL:http://www.iup.com/order.cfm?bookno=PC&action=info&J=J] AB: Abstract Considers Professor David Livingstone Smith's explication of Freud's theory of consciousness. The author proceeds by seeking to provide as accurate a picture as he can of Freud's conception. Wherever it seems necessary, he attempts to improve on what he has written previously, and takes the opportunity to reinforce the case for constructing Freud as he has. Much agreement is to be expected between Smith's and the author's understanding of Freud's account, because Smith has studied six articles of the present series and expressed his indebtedness to them. In contrast to the author discussed in article XI of this series, Smith and the author are speaking of many of the same textual materials. But, this does not mean that they are in total agreement. For example, Smith does not consider to be real a problem with Freud's theory that the author raised in the second article of this series: Freud considered conscious thoughts meaningful, his theory requires their meaning be transferred to them from unconscious thoughts, which transpire outside the perception-consciousness system, but the theory does not make this transfer possible. (PsycINFO Database Record (c) 2004 APA, all rights reserved) Record 11 of 34 DN: Database Name PsycINFO (1840-Current) TI: Title The experiential presence of objects to perceptual consciousness: Wilfrid Sellars, sense impressions, and perceptual takings AU: Author Natsoulas, Thomas SO: Source Journal of Mind & Behavior. Vol 23(3), Sum 2002, pp. 293-316 RL: Resource Location [URL:http://www.ume.maine.edu/~jmb/welcome.html] AB: Abstract Discussion of W. Sellars's rediscovery of experiential presence continues with special reference to J. McDowell's and J.E Rosenberg's recent articles on Sellars's understanding of perception, and a later effort by Sellars to cast light on the intimate relation between sensing and perceptual taking. Five main sections respectively summarize my earlier discussion of Sellars's account of experiential presence, draw on Rosenberg's explication of two Sellarsian modes of responding to sense impressions, consider McDowell's claim that Sellars's perceptual takings are shapings of sensory consciousness, introduce Sellars's Kantian late account of experiential presence, and return critically to McDowell's thesis: Sellars's perceptual takings, notwithstanding their being purely conceptual actualizations, give us awareness of the very pinkness of a pink ice cube. (PsycINFO Database Record (c) 2004 APA, all rights reserved) (journal abstract ) Record 12 of 34 DN: Database Name PsycINFO (1840-Current) TI: Title On the intrinsic nature of states of consciousness: O'Shaughnessy and the mythology of the attention AU: Author Natsoulas, Thomas SO: Source Consciousness & Emotion. Vol 3(1), 2002, pp. 35-64 RL: Resource Location [URL:http://www.benjamins.com/cgi-bin/t_seriesview.cgi?series=C%26 E] AB: Abstract What are the states of consciousness in themselves, those pulses of mentality that follow one upon another in tight succession and constitute the stream of consciousness? William James conceives of each of them as being, typically, a complex unitary awareness that instantiates many features and takes a multiplicity of objects. In contrast, Brian O'Shaughnessy claims that the basic durational component of the stream of consciousness is the attention, which he understands to be something like a psychic space that is simultaneously occupied by several experiences. Whereas, according to the first conception, emotion is a feature of a temporal segment of the stream of consciousness and colors through and through each consciousness state that instantiates it, the second conception considers an emotion to be a distinct one of a system of simultaneous experiences that interact with each other, for example, limiting each other's number and intensity. Among other matters discussed is the two theorists' mutually contrasting conception of how the non-inferential awareness which we have of our states of consciousness is accomplished. (PsycINFO Database Record (c) 2004 APA, all rights reserved) (journal abstract ) Record 13 of 34 DN: Database Name PsycINFO (1840-Current) TI: Title Missing the experiential presence of environmental objects: A construal of immediate sensible representations as conceptual AU: Author Natsoulas, Thomas SO: Source Journal of Mind & Behavior. Vol 23(4), Fal 2002, pp. 325-350 RL: Resource Location [URL:http://www.ume.maine.edu/~jmb/welcome.html] AB: Abstract By means of a comparative study of W. Sellar's Kantian approach to the problem of experiential presence, J. McDowell (1998) gives a reading of I. Kant on intentionality understood to be "the directedness of subjective states and episodes toward objects." The current author addresses only one of the products of McDowell's indirect approach, namely, what he understands to be McDowell's own conception of immediate sensible representation. Selecting from the complex fabric of McDowell's discussion, the author states that only the thread that expresses directly McDowell's own account seems to be not consistent with McDowell's own purposes. For McDowell claims to be moving us toward how we should be thinking about internationality, since more than anybody else, McDowell's major influence, who is Kant, is on the right track. (PsycINFO Database Record (c) 2004 APA, all rights reserved) Record 14 of 34 DN: Database Name PsycINFO (1840-Current) TI: Title The case for intrinsic theory: V. Some arguments from James's Varieties AU: Author Natsoulas, Thomas SO: Source Journal of Mind & Behavior. Vol 22(1), Win 2001, pp. 41-68 RL: Resource Location [URL:http://www.ume.maine.edu/~jmb/welcome.html] AB: Abstract Discusses consciousness and intrinsic theory using the viewpoint of William James's The Varieties of Religious Experience. The present author brings out further arguments in favor of the kind of understanding of consciousness or inner awareness that James explicitly opposed in The Principles of Psychology. The alternative, appendage kind of account that James advanced there for consciousness stands in marked contrast to intrinsic theory: by requiring that having inner awareness of any mental-occurrence instance must take the form of a separate mental-occurrence instance directed on the first. Intrinsic theory holds instead that every conscious mental-occurrence instance possesses a phenomenological structure that includes reference to that very instance itself. (PsycINFO Database Record (c) 2004 APA, all rights reserved) Record 15 of 34 DN: Database Name PsycINFO (1840-Current) TI: Title The case for intrinsic theory: VI. incompatibilities within the stream of consciousness AU: Author Natsoulas, Thomas SO: Source Journal of Mind & Behavior. Vol 22(2), Spr 2001, pp. 119-146 RL: Resource Location [URL:http://www.ume.maine.edu/~jmb/welcome.html] AB: Abstract In The Varieties of Religious Experience (W. James, 1902/1982), James explores a kind of dividedness that can exist within the stream of consciousness -- "the divided self." This condition of the stream consists in crucial part of a phenomenological heterogeneity, inconsistency, discordance, or division of which disapproving notice is taken subjectively. The pertinent discordance exists among states of consciousness that comprise the same stream, is evident directly to inner awareness, and is not necessarily a matter of positing or inferring the existence of a second stream of consciousness or an unconscious mental life. Typically, intrinsic theorists of inner awareness -- or the immediate awareness we all have of at least some of our own mental-occurrence instances--disagree with appendage theorists concerning, inter alia, what the first-hand evidence reveals about inner awareness. The authors proffers a hypothesis that should help to explain why the first-person reports of appendage theorists contradict intrinsic theory with regard to inner awareness. The author's hypothesis derives from James's discussion in Varieties of the not uncommon divided-self phenomenon. (PsycINFO Database Record (c) 2004 APA, all rights reserved) Record 16 of 34 DN: Database Name PsycINFO (1840-Current) TI: Title On the intrinsic nature of states of consciousness: Attempted inroads from the first-person perspective AU: Author Natsoulas, Thomas SO: Source Journal of Mind & Behavior. Vol 22(3), Sum 2001, pp. 219-248 RL: Resource Location [URL:http://www.ume.maine.edu/~jmb/welcome.html] AB: Abstract Discusses the intrinsic nature of states of consciousness. Streams of consciousness, as discussed by W. James (1899), are each made up of states of consciousness 1 at a time in tight temporal succession, except when a stream stops flowing for a period of time. Although unitary, a state of consciousness often has many objects, which have some kind of existence, past, present, or future, or which are nonexistent, merely apparent. The problem concerning the intrinsic nature of states of consciousness is what they are themselves, not what they are about or what they may seem to be about. The author argues that attempts to determine the intrinsic properties of states of consciousness are well advised to attend to the individual's inner awareness of them. Any true statement about a state of consciousness that one may succeed in formulating from the 1st-person perspective should be considered a fact concerning a brain state. Also, various ingredients belonging to a state of consciousness are integrated together in a unitary state. The claim that finding states of consciousness firsthand is illusory has several problems. (PsycINFO Database Record (c) 2004 APA, all rights reserved) Record 17 of 34 DN: Database Name PsycINFO (1840-Current) TI: Title The concrete state: The basic components of James's stream of consciousness AU: Author Natsoulas, Thomas SO: Source Journal of Mind & Behavior. Vol 22(4), Fal 2001, pp. 427-450 RL: Resource Location [URL:http://www.ume.maine.edu/~jmb/welcome.html] AB: Abstract Discusses the basic components of W. James's views (1890) concerning stream of consciousness. A sympathetic reading of James's reports of his personal firsthand evidence shows that many of his claims are acceptable and consistent with a thesis fundamental to his perspective: that is, that a stream of consciousness consists of a succession, 1 at a time, of unitary states and all of the other mental occurrences that are conscious are features of such states. Part II of this article is 2002-12690-006. (PsycINFO Database Record (c) 2004 APA, all rights reserved) Record 18 of 34 DN: Database Name PsycINFO (1840-Current) TI: Title The concrete state continued AU: Author Natsoulas, Thomas SO: Source Journal of Mind & Behavior. Vol 22(4), Fal 2001, pp. 451-474 RL: Resource Location [URL:http://www.ume.maine.edu/~jmb/welcome.html] AB: Abstract Discusses the basic components of W. James's views (1890) concerning stream of consciousness. Examination of James's account of the sense of personal identity leads to the specific states of consciousness that he called individually "the present, judging Thought." These states, which are the inner awarenesses, remembrances, and appropriations of other states of consciousness in the same stream, are supposed to provide individuals with a sense of their own diachronic continuity. According to James, they are the only "I" that there is. James in effect assigned this job to the total brain process. Embodying all the information required, it is this physical process that is proposed to produce each Thought full-blown. Part I of this article is 2002-12690-005. (PsycINFO Database Record (c) 2004 APA, all rights reserved) Record 19 of 34 DN: Database Name PsycINFO (1840-Current) TI: Title The Freudian conscious AU: Author Natsoulas, Thomas SO: Source Consciousness & Emotion. Special Affective qualia and the subjective dimension. Vol 2(1), 2001, pp. 1-28 RL: Resource Location [URL:http://www.benjamins.com/cgi-bin/t_seriesview.cgi?series=C%26 E] AB: Abstract To reduce the likelihood that psychology will develop in a deeply flawed manner, the present article seeks to provide an introduction to Freud's conception of consciousness because, for among other reasons, his general theory is highly influential in science and culture and among the best understood by clinicians and experimentalists. The theory is complex and all of its major parts have a bearing on one another; indeed, consciousness has a central place in the total conceptual structure--as is argued, in effect, throughout the present article. The discussion focuses mainly on how conscious psychical processes differ from processes of the psychical apparatus that do not instantiate the Freudian attribute of consciousness. This intrinsic attribute that belongs to every conscious psychical process is seen as including, along with qualitative content, an unmediated, witting awareness of the psychical process that is directed upon itself. (PsycINFO Database Record (c) 2004 APA, all rights reserved) Record 20 of 34 DN: Database Name PsycINFO (1840-Current) TI: Title The stream of consciousness: XXV. Awareness as commentary (Part I) AU: Author Natsoulas, Thomas SO: Source Imagination, Cognition & Personality. Vol 21(4), 2001-2002, pp. 347-366 RL: Resource Location [URL:http://baywood.com/search/PreviewJournal.asp?qsRecord=4] AB: Abstract This two-part article is propaedeutic to considering subsequently Weiskrantz's "commentary" conception of consciousness: from the perspective that James bequeathed to us more than a century ago. Weiskrantz has sought to render plausible a general account of awareness that resembles the "Intellectualist" notion of mind to which James had objected in The Principles. Whereas the central problem he addresses is where in the brain James's consciousness stream flows, Weiskrantz holds all awareness, even pain, is commentary. Contrary to how it may appear to the person himself or herself, every state of consciousness is no more than a kind of behavioral response--covert, overt, or incipient--bringing something or other under some heading. Although Weiskrantz formulates his concept of awareness in terms of operations that get a subject to report so the experimenter can judge whether the subject is aware of something in particular, Weiskrantz rejects all strategies that seek to theoretically eliminate awareness. Nevertheless, he proposes awareness to consist simply of the actual or potential delivery of a report. (PsycINFO Database Record (c) 2004 APA, all rights reserved) (journal abstract ) Record 21 of 34 DN: Database Name PsycINFO (1840-Current) TI: Title The stream of consciousness: XXIV. James contra the intellectualists (second part) AU: Author Natsoulas, Thomas SO: Source Imagination, Cognition & Personality. Vol 21(3), 2001-2002, pp. 253-272 RL: Resource Location [URL:http://baywood.com/search/PreviewJournal.asp?qsRecord=4] AB: Abstract James presented a number of compelling arguments against those theorists whom he called the "Intellectualists": a) for holding that mental states of the mundane Jamesian qualitative kind cannot provide us with our awareness of relations; and b) for introducing purely conceptualizing mental acts to do the job from on high. In his classic account of mental life, James found no use for purely conceptualizing mental states, whether in relation to our awareness of objective relations or in relation to our awareness of anything else. All of the mental states that constitute the stream of consciousness--and therefore, in James's view, all mental states that occur in us--are of the qualitative/cognitive kind, whether they are minimal conceivings of the sensation kind or they have the most abstract objects. I continue in the present article to discuss James's responses to the Intellectualists. I discuss in particular how James addressed their claim that an account of the apprehension of universals requires the theoretical introduction of mental states purportedly resembling universals, namely, purely conceptualizing mental acts. (PsycINFO Database Record (c) 2004 APA, all rights reserved) (journal abstract ) Record 22 of 34 DN: Database Name PsycINFO (1840-Current) TI: Title Freud and consciousness: X. The place of consciousness in Freud's science AU: Author Natsoulas, Thomas SO: Source Psychoanalysis & Contemporary Thought. Vol 23(4), Fal 2000, pp. 525-561 RL: Resource Location [URL:http://www.iup.com/order.cfm?bookno=PC&action=info&J=J] AB: Abstract This article focuses on the place that Freud explicitly assigned to consciousness within his science. Of central concern are the conscious psychical processes, which occur in the perception-consciousness system, possess individually both qualitative and cognitive contents, and include conscious awareness each one of itself, along with whatever else each may be an awareness of. The quality of being conscious, which every conscious psychical process possesses, is intrinsic to each conscious psychical process; nothing more than it itself needs to occur in order for the quality to be instantiated. Direct acquaintance with conscious psychical processes provides the analogical basis for positing unconscious psychical processes; these help to explain the occurrence of psychical and behavioral happening consciously accessible by sensory perception or inner awareness. Every unconscious psychical process is, so to speak, an instance of a "truncated" consciousness; i.e., its owner undergoes therein nonqualitative and nonreflexive awareness of something or as though of something. Although the quality of being conscious is not essential to the psychical, it is no less a property of natural processes than any other property a psychical process possesses. (PsycINFO Database Record (c) 2004 APA, all rights reserved) Record 23 of 34 DN: Database Name PsycINFO (1840-Current) TI: Title Consciousness and conscience AU: Author Natsoulas, Thomas SO: Source Journal of Mind & Behavior. Vol 21(4), Fal 2000, pp. 327-352 RL: Resource Location [URL:http://www.ume.maine.edu/~jmb/welcome.html] AB: Abstract Discusses aspects and meanings of the words "conscious"and "consciousness", including that of the "intrapersonal together sense". Whereas the interpersonal sense of consciousness picks out a certain kind of relation that exists, has existed, or will exist between 2 or a few people, the intrapersonal together sense refers to a process instantiated wholly by a single person yet analogous to that particular interpersonal relation. In addition to the interpersonal sense and the intrapersonal together sense, this article distinguishes the related concept of "consciousness in the guilty sense" which has reference to a subcategory of consciousness in the intrapersonal together sense. A person conscious in the guilty sense has come to judge that he or she has committed or is committing now a legal or moral transgression-- this kind of consciousness turning into an application of "conscience" insofar as the judgment passed involves moral self-condemnation and produces feelings of guilt. All of the above are mutually similar kinds of consciousness and they are cases of "awareness- with." (PsycINFO Database Record (c) 2004 APA, all rights reserved) Record 24 of 34 DN: Database Name PsycINFO (1840-Current) TI: Title The stream of consciousness: XXI. Blindsight and states of consciousness AU: Author Natsoulas, Thomas SO: Source Imagination, Cognition & Personality. Vol 20(1), 2000-2001, pp. 71-95 RL: Resource Location [URL:http://baywood.com/search/PreviewJournal.asp?qsRecord=4] AB: Abstract Blindsight research provides an opportunity to place W. James's account of consciousness in an empirical context that is attracting much comment from psychologists. The author spells out an interpretation of blindsight--neurological phenomenon resulting from visual-cortical lesions--in keeping with James's conception of the stream of consciousness in The Principles of Psychology, in order shed light on the conception of consciousness that James was developing. Consistently with James's general theory, no role is assigned to unconscious mental occurrences in this Jamesian interpretation of blindsight. Accordingly, the special deficiency of blindsight consists in the total brain process, bringing states of consciousness into existence whose intrinsic visual-perceptual dimension is inaccessible or unreliably accessible to immediate apprehension. (PsycINFO Database Record (c) 2004 APA, all rights reserved) Record 25 of 34 DN: Database Name PsycINFO (1840-Current) TI: Title The stream of consciousness: XXIII. James Contra the intellectualists (first part) AU: Author Natsoulas, Thomas SO: Source Imagination, Cognition & Personality. Vol 20(4), 2000-2001, pp. 383-404 RL: Resource Location [URL:http://baywood.com/search/PreviewJournal.asp?qsRecord=4] AB: Abstract W. James distinguished the states of consciousness that successively constitute a stream of consciousness from how they appear to inner awareness. For one thing, the stream has a discrete temporal structure whereas its basic durational components inwardly seem continuous, each with the next one: partly because the stream never abruptly changes in all of the features of its content. States of consciousness that James called "transitive" apprehend objective relations existing between items apprehended successively. The Intellectualists claimed that states of the mundane Jamesian qualitative kind cannot provide awareness of relations and they introduced purely conceptualizing mental states to do the job from on high. James formulated a number of cogent opposing arguments: some of these are discussed in the present article. These arguments may well prove useful, too, against an understanding of consciousness that has been advanced recently in a neuropsychological context. More extremely than the Intellectualists, the advocate of this conception maintains that any mental stream, whether animal or human, consists entirely of acts of commentary. (PsycINFO Database Record (c) 2004 APA, all rights reserved) Record 26 of 34 DN: Database Name PsycINFO (1840-Current) TI: Title The stream of consciousness: XXII. Apprehension and the feeling aspect AU: Author Natsoulas, Thomas SO: Source Imagination, Cognition & Personality. Vol 20(3), 2000-2001, pp. 275-295 RL: Resource Location [URL:http://baywood.com/search/PreviewJournal.asp?qsRecord=4] AB: Abstract This article discusses the meaning and function of the feeling aspect that, according to W. James, every state of consciousness possesses. From a previous article, the author continues here an effort to spell out how the feeling aspect and a cognitive aspect--which, too, was proposed to characterize all pulses of mentality--belong together to a single integral whole. Every state of consciousness is both a feeling and a mental apprehension of something, or at least as though of something. Although states of consciousness vary in veridicality, no state of consciousness is more or less cognitive than any other. Nor is any state of consciousness more abstract, less finite, than any another, less of a concrete feeling. Even an awareness of something universal or general is a "perfectly determinate, singular, and transient thing.... a perishing segment of thought's stream, consubstantial with other facts of sensibility." The feeling aspect is the experiential, qualitative way in which--or form by which--a state of consciousness feels the totality of items, properties, events, relations, and so on, that it apprehends or seems to apprehend. (PsycINFO Database Record (c) 2004 APA, all rights reserved) Record 27 of 34 DN: Database Name PsycINFO (1840-Current) TI: Title On the intrinsic nature of states of consciousness: Further considerations in the light of James's conception AU: Author Natsoulas, Thomas SO: Source Consciousness & Emotion. Vol 1(1), 2000, pp. 139-166 RL: Resource Location [URL:http://www.benjamins.com/cgi-bin/t_seriesview.cgi?series=C%26 E] AB: Abstract How are the states of consciousness intrinsically so that they all qualify as "feelings" in W. James's generic sense? The author restricts his topic mainly to a certain characteristic that belongs to each of those pulses of mentality that successively make up James's stream of consciousness. Certain statements of James's are intended to pick out the variable "width" belonging to a stream of consciousness as it flows. Attention to this proposed property brings the author to a discussion of (1) the unitary character of each of the states of consciousness however complex they may frequently be and (2) how to conceive of their complexity without recourse to a misleading spatial metaphor. (PsycINFO Database Record (c) 2004 APA, all rights reserved) Record 28 of 34 DN: Database Name PsycINFO (1840-Current) TI: Title An ecological and phenomenological perspective on consciousness and perception: Contact with the world at the very heart of the being of consciousness AU: Author Natsoulas, Thomas SO: Source Review of General Psychology. Vol 3(3), Sep 1999, pp. 224-245 RL: Resource Location [URL:http://www.apa.org/journals/gpr.html] AB: Abstract Owing to the intentional nature of consciousness, people possess a special kind of contact with the real world. They apprehend part of it in a qualitative and cognitive manner at the ontological level suitably described as corresponding to the psychological. At the core of the visual system's molar activities, a stream of visual awareness flows and is the very form wherein direct visual reference to the world is accomplished. Also a function of the visual system, when it is operating in the mode called "viewing" or "reflective seeing," is one's immediate apprehension of visual perceptual experience per se. Using an approach that draws on both ecological and phenomenological thought, the author seeks to make progress toward a conceptual structure for consciousness. (PsycINFO Database Record (c) 2004 APA, all rights reserved) (journal abstract ) Record 29 of 34 DN: Database Name PsycINFO (1840-Current) TI: Title The concept of consciousness-sub-6: The general state meaning AU: Author Natsoulas, Thomas SO: Source Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour. Vol 29(1), Mar 1999, pp. 59-87 RL: Resource Location [URL:http://www.blackwellpublishers.co.uk/asp/journal.asp?ref=0021 -8308] AB: Abstract Considered here is the last one of the six basic concepts of consciousness that The Oxford English Dictionary identifies in its several entries under consciousness. The referent of the sixth concept, which I call "consciousness-sub-6," is rightly understood to be a certain general operating mode of the mind. Any psychological account of consciousness-sub-6 must distinguish this operating mode from (a) the "particular consciousness or awarenesses," i.e., the specific thoughts, feelings, perceptions, intentions, and the like (including William James's succession of total states of consciousness), that occur while the mind is so operating, and from (b) the other, alternative, general operating modes of the mind: such as those that are sometimes in force in place of consciousness-sub-6, when one is awake. (PsycINFO Database Record (c) 2004 APA, all rights reserved) Record 30 of 34 DN: Database Name PsycINFO (1840-Current) TI: Title A commentary system for consciousness?! AU: Author Natsoulas, Thomas SO: Source Journal of Mind & Behavior. Vol 20(2), Spr 1999, pp. 155-181 RL: Resource Location [URL:http://www.ume.maine.edu/~jmb/welcome.html] AB: Abstract Critiques a proposal that L. Weiskrantz published in his book, Consciousness Lost and Found: A Neurophysiological Exploration (1997), on brain-damaged individuals. It is a proposal regarding the locus, nature, and character of consciousness in general. Every instance of being conscious, or aware, or having experience of anything (O), is supposed to be identical to either one of three kinds of activity of a commentary system in the brain that correspond to the Skinnerian distinction between overt, covert, and incipient responses. Any human or animal who is experiencing O at the present moment is therein either (a) commenting on O to someone else; (b) commenting on O to himself or herself, overtly or covertly; or (c) occurrently tending to comment on O, overtly or covertly, either to someone else or to himself or herself. This third form of experience of O is made up of a certain portion of a process in the commentary system that constitutes overt or covert commenting on O. Although the identification of awareness with commentary is Weiskrantz's stated preference, the current author questions Weiskrantz's implication that commentary behavior is not required equally by different kinds of awareness. (PsycINFO Database Record (c) 2004 APA, all rights reserved) Record 31 of 34 DN: Database Name PsycINFO (1840-Current) TI: Title A rediscovery of presence AU: Author Natsoulas, Thomas SO: Source Journal of Mind & Behavior. Vol 20(1), Win 1999, pp. 17-42 RL: Resource Location [URL:http://www.ume.maine.edu/~jmb/welcome.html] AB: Abstract When we see Wilfrid Sellars's favorite object, an ice cube pink through and through, we see the very pinkness of it. Inner awareness of our visual experience finds the ice cube to be experientially present, not merely representationally present to our consciousness. Its pinkness and other properties are present not merely metaphorically, not merely in the sense that the experience represents or is an occurrent belief in the ice cube's being there before us. Despite his behavioristic inclinations, Sellars acknowledges experiential presence and gives an account of it in terms of a perceptual experience's having two intrinsic components, a sensation and a conceptual response to the sensation that ultimately refers to the sensation although it normally takes the sensation for the environmental item that produced it. Problems with Sellars's account include the inadequacy of the causal and referential relations postulated between the two components of a perceptual experience, and the experimentally demonstrated fact (A. Michotte et al, 1964/1991) that, although sensations may be necessary for perceptual experience, experiential presence of a particular environmental property does not always require corresponding sensations. (PsycINFO Database Record (c) 2004 APA, all rights reserved) Record 32 of 34 DN: Database Name PsycINFO (1840-Current) TI: Title The case of intrinsic theory: IV. An argument from how conscious mental-occurrence instances seem AU: Author Natsoulas, Thomas SO: Source Journal of Mind & Behavior. Vol 20(3), Sum 1999, pp. 257-276 RL: Resource Location [URL:http://www.ume.maine.edu/~jmb/welcome.html] AB: Abstract D. Woodruff Smith maintains that, within any objectivating act that is its object, inner awareness (i.e., direct occurrent awareness of the act) is inextricably interwoven with the outer awareness (i.e., occurrent awareness of or as though of something else) that is involved in the act. The author provides an examination of arguments Woodruff Smith proffers pro an understanding of inner awareness as intrinsic. He gives attention only to one of Woodruff Smith's arguments, and his discussion focuses largely on how D. M. Rosenthal, who holds instead that inner awareness is accomplished by a separate mental-occurrence instance, has interpreted the empirical evidence that Woodruff Smith cites. Woodruff Smith considers how a conscious mental-occurrence instance seems to its owner to be empirical evidence that lends support to intrinsic theory of inner awareness. When one introspects a mental-occurrence instance, one finds a single unified experience, not two of them as Rosenthal proposes. Rosenthal accepts this firsthand evidence as tending to support intrinsic theory, but tries to explain the appearances away, mentioning G.E. Moore's description of consciousness as "transparent." (PsycINFO Database Record (c) 2004 APA, all rights reserved) Record 33 of 34 DN: Database Name PsycINFO (1840-Current) TI: Title The stream of consciousness: XX: A non-ecological conception AU: Author Natsoulas, Thomas SO: Source Imagination, Cognition & Personality. Vol 19(1), 1999-2000, pp. 71-90 RL: Resource Location [URL:http://baywood.com/search/PreviewJournal.asp?qsRecord=4] AB: Abstract Contrasts James's views on consciousness in "The Principles of Psychology (1890, 1950) with those of S. K. Langer in "Mind: An Essay on Human Feeling" (1967). The author suggests that James's discussion of consciousness seeks to express a non-egological conception of the subject matter. James is seen as consistently refusing to adopt any theory according to which consciousness is brought into being by something more than the processes of the brain; there exists no mental spring or source from which the mental stream flows or has its origin; the ongoing activity of the brain, without knowing what it does, produces mechanically one state of consciousness after another. In contrast, Langer's descriptions of the organism as that which feels may be a way of implicitly introducing a physical ego, which does all that a metaphysical subject or ego is supposed to do. A brain center that, as Langer holds, receives impressions of physiological processes above a certain limen and, by apprehending them, renders these processes into states of consciousness, is viewed as a physical ego. (PsycINFO Database Record (c) 2004 APA, all rights reserved) Record 34 of 34 DN: Database Name PsycINFO (1840-Current) TI: Title Virtual objects AU: Author Natsoulas, Thomas SO: Source Journal of Mind & Behavior. Vol 20(4), Fal 1999, pp. 357-377 RL: Resource Location [URL:http://www.ume.maine.edu/~jmb/welcome.html] AB: Abstract Comments on the concept of "virtual objects" as described by J. J. Gibson in The Ecological Approach to Visual Perception (1979, 1986). Gibson contends that objects are both perceived and not perceived through their images; examples include pictures of places and events. In contrast to Gibson's views, experiences undergone in the process of perceiving pictures of things are not identical with perceiving the things themselves. The cases of a photograph of a tree, a bleeding heart in an inkblot, very small and very distant surfaces, an optical tunnel, shadows, an invisibly supported objects, and movie scenes all point to problems with Gibson's concept. Visually perceived objects are, have been, or will be actual parts of the single world we inhabit, or they have no existence. Adoption of Gibson's view that we visually perceive imaginary virtual objects extends the sense of "visual perceiving" to a point where the phrase loses usefulness for the field of psychology. (PsycINFO Database Record (c) 2004 APA, all rights reserved)